We can prove there is no uniform distribution on $Q$ .
Proof. Assume there exists such a uniform distribution, that is, there
exists $a \ge 0$ such that $P(X = q) = a$ for every $q \in Q$ .
Observe that, since $Q$ is countable, by countable additivity of $P$ :
$$
1 = P(X \in Q)=\sum_{q \in Q} P(X = q) = \sum_{q \in Q} a
$$
Observe that if $a = 0$ , $\sum_{q \in Q} a = 0$ . Similarly, if $a > 0$ ,
$\sum_{q \in Q} a = \infty$ . Contradiction.
Let's analyze.
The second part of this reasoning is remotely resemblant to the following
iterated limit:
$$
\lim_{n\rightarrow\infty} n \left[ \lim_{m\rightarrow\infty} \frac{1}{m}
\right] = \lim_{n\rightarrow\infty} n\; 0 = 0
$$ First
define uniform probabilities. It's easy to see that these will become zero if
the initial segment becomes infinite. Then sum up. Evidently the sum then
must be zero as well. We have learnt, though, that iterated limits may be
understood in a quite different way. Due to the following Theorem, proved
elsewhere by this author:
$$
\lim_{x\rightarrow a} \left[ \lim_{y\rightarrow b} F(x,y) \right] =
\lim_{(x,y)\rightarrow (a,b)} F(x,y)
$$
Translated to the present case of interest, with $F(m,n) = n.1/m$ :
$$
\lim_{n\rightarrow\infty} \left[ \lim_{m\rightarrow\infty} n.\frac{1}{m}
\right] = \lim_{(m,n)\rightarrow\infty} \left[ n . \frac{1}{m} \right]
$$
However, the numbers $m$ and $n$ must be equal, $m = n$ , because they
denote one and the same upper bound for the initial segment of the naturals at
hand. Therefore we actually have:
$$
\lim_{n\rightarrow\infty} \left[ n . \frac{1}{n} \right] =
\lim_{n\rightarrow\infty} \left[ 1 \right] = 1
$$
I think the twist is clear now. But ah, the trouble with understanding all this
might be something else as well ..
The sum of infinitely many zeroes in our tentative probability theory is equal
to one. The Riemann sum in infinitesimal calculus - mind infinitesimal -
is equal to one as well. Could it be that the existence of infinitesimals is
consequently denied in common mathematics - because, especially in calculus,
they "aren't needed anymore". But as soon as we add a twist to probability
theory, it seems that they turn up again.
As has been said in the beginning, our tentative probability theory is actually
equivalent
with Natural Densities. The probability that a natural number is e.g. seven is
exactly zero, just meaning that the density of seven in the naturals is zero.
Yet the density of a natural being an even number is not zero: it equals $1/2$.
In fact, it has no sense to distinguish Uniform Probabilities on the Naturals
from Natural Densities from Finitary Cardinalities. Maybe somewhat exaggerated,
but one gets the idea. The redundancy, as a consequence of Infinitum Actu
Non Datur may be summarized loud and clear:
$$
\mbox{Finitary Cardinalities} = \mbox{Uniform Probabilities} =
\mbox{Natural Densities}
$$